Stop
me if you’ve heard this one before. Through no fault of your own,
you find yourself stuck on a deserted island or in a snowed-in cabin
with an infant. You are not the infant’s legal guardian. Do
you have any obligation to feed the infant? If you say yes, then you
have just shown that a pregnant person is obligated to carry the
pregnancy even in cases of rape.
If
your immediate response is “Wait a minute here!” you are not
alone. If this is not your immediate reaction,
it should be. The basic
scenario falls apart at the slightest touch. Merely feeding an infant
is nothing like pregnancy with the attendant symptoms and side
effects and an infant doesn’t take nutrition directly
from a person’s body. The
deserted island scenario is so unlike pregnancy, let alone pregnancy
resulting from rape, that it is a wonder this scenario and others
like it are a favorite among the slavers.
But
what if a scenario like this can worked into something that fairly
closely resembles a pregnancy caused by rape? Could
the scenario be so easily defeated then? Enter
“De
Facto Guardian and Abortion: A Response to the Strongest Violinist”
by Stephen Wagner. Wagner is writing for some
slavers called the “Justice
for All Philosophy Team,” so this paper is the result of a group
project. Wagner is building on previous versions of the snowed-in
cabin story proposed by
Francis
Beckwith and Rich
Poupard. So “De Facto
Guardian” is probably about
as strong a version of this
scenario as
we are going to get.
The
violinist of the title is a reference to the famous analogy proposed
by Judith Jarvis Thomson in her “A
Defense of Abortion.” The
“strongest” violinist probably references the fact that it is
widely acknowledged that Thomson’s analogy has its clearest
application to pregnancies resulting from rape. Wagner
and his team are
especially concerned with her argument, and this paper is
trying to refute it. So “De
Facto Guardian” is best read as a response to Thomson. Though I
don’t believe their response
successfully refutes
Thomson, assuming they do, it remains to be seen if and how their
arguments might affect other attempts to show abortion is
permissible, including my
own.
The basic strategy of Wagner’s argument is take things
step-by-step. The initial story hardly resembles pregnancy at all,
let alone pregnancy caused by rape. The object is to see if the
person has any moral obligation to act at this stage. If so, then we
proceed to the next step to see if that obligation still holds. If
so, we proceed to the next step, and so on until we have arrived at
the point the scenario most closely resembles pregnancy. Wagner goes
even further and ponders whether the obligation holds even in cases
where the scenario is actually worse than pregnancy.
This means we are faced with a two-fold question by Wagner’s
argument. The first question is, “Does someone have a moral
obligation in this scenario?” The second question is how far that
obligation, if any, extends given how onerous the conditions become.
This means that if we can definitively answer there is no moral
obligation in the first place, we need not consider how burdensome
the conditions are. However, even if we do allow there is a moral
obligation in the basic case, if we can definitively answer the
conditions have become so taxing that the obligation no longer holds,
we are justified in stopping at that point. If this point falls short
of the scenario most closely resembling pregnancy, then Wagner’s
argument fails. By parity of reasoning, the person who becomes
pregnant as a result of rape is not obligated to carry the pregnancy
to term.
The Basic Story
Mary,
who gave birth a week ago, wakes up one morning and discovers she is
in a cabin that has been snowed in. She finds a note telling
her that
she is stuck in the
cabin for six weeks, that both she and her child are safe, and there
is plenty of food. She searches the cabin and discovers a week-old
infant, but it is not her child. She also discovers there is
enough formula to feed an infant for three months, along
with “a huge store of food and a ready source of water.”
Six
weeks later, the police show up and rescue her. They inform her that
her kidnappers were some behavior psychologists from the local
university and ask if
anyone else is in the cabin. Mary answers, “There was.”
Concerned, the police search the cabin and find the body of the
infant. It is determined the infant died from starvation. The infant
formula was not touched.
The
question before us is whether Mary did something wrong here.
Specifically, did she have an obligation to feed the infant while
they were stuck in the cabin?
Wagner
takes it as a given that Mary was wrong to let the infant starve. On
the initial reading, I suspect most people would think letting the
child starve was morally
outrageous.
Absent
justification or excuse then, it would seem that Mary was obligated
to feed the child and did something seriously wrong by letting it
starve. But once the emotional reaction subsides and we think about
this scenario more rationally, should we think Mary was obligated to
feed the infant? No. Why not? Because Mary clearly would have been
justified in leaving the cabin even at the risk of letting the infant
starve.
If
this seems like a radical idea, let’s think this through. Mary was
definitely kidnapped; possibly
the infant was also.
She
had
no assurance other than the note that she would be freed at all. The
note insinuated her child was with her in the cabin; that
was a lie. And a “huge” supply of food and a three-month
store of infant formula? For what was only supposed to be a six-week
captivity? Mary may not have
known
exactly what was
going on, but it would be reasonable for her to have
suspected
she would
not
be
freed in six weeks, if
at all.
Presumably
only the kidnappers knew
where she was
and anyone who
tried
finding
her would not have
known
where to begin looking. Finally, she did
have an obligation to find out what happened to her own child.
Furthermore, if Mary did try to escape, it would not have been
prudent to take the infant with her. Not only would the child have
hindered her chances of successful escape, taking it with her would
have only put the infant in further danger. If she successfully
escaped, hopefully the authorities could be directed back to the
cabin in time to keep the child from starving. If not, then for all
Mary knows, both she and the infant were going to die anyway, so
either way the child would not be any worse off.
Now
let’s turn back to the question of whether Mary was obligated to
feed the infant. Since Mary was
not morally obligated to stay in the cabin, there
is no reasonable case Mary was
obligated to feed the infant, for
whom,
after all, Mary
had
no responsibility.
We
haven’t gotten anywhere even remotely resembling pregnancy, and it
seems we have stopped Wagner’s strategy before it has even started.
It would be tempting to rest our laurels here and move on to
considering less absurd slaver arguments. But let’s not be so hasty
here. After all, the scenario can be modified so that Mary and the
infant are placed in a situation that precludes any practical means
of escape. Examples might include
a deserted island, a deep sea base, or a space capsule.
Would
so modifying the scenario change anything? Perhaps, but our basic
insight that Mary was
justified in leaving the cabin still holds. Even if Mary couldn’t
escape for all practical purposes, she would have
still
been
justified in doing anything that
would have
allowed
her to escape had
the opportunity presented
itself,
even
if it risks the infant’s death.
Under
the modified scenario, was
Mary obligated to feed the infant? No doubt Wagner would say she was.
I highly suspect most people would agree on the initial reading.
Subject to the above
provision,
I’m also
inclined to agree Mary was
obligated. And
once the emotional reaction subsides, there
doesn’t seem to be a reasonable case that Mary was
not obligated to feed the infant. So, unless someone presents a
reasonable case that Mary was
not obligated to feed the infant (in which case I will rewrite this
entire essay), I will take it as a given that our intuition in this
case is justified. In other words, subject to the above provision,
Mary was
obligated to feed the infant in our
modified scenario.
We
are in basic agreement with
Wagner in
the “formula” case in section Ib,
though in our
case, this is subject to the provision that she was
justified in trying to escape. We
disagree
sharply with
Wagner in
the “no formula” case of section Ic.
It
seems to me that the fact
of an obligation is severable from the scope
of the obligation. Unless
we wish to be perfect, the obligation to give to the poor does not
extend to giving so much we no longer have enough to live on.
This
means we can set aside the discussion of where the obligation no
longer holds because it is too taxing for the time being. So
at
this point, I am going to skip ahead to
Wagner’s discussion of why Mary was
obligated to feed the infant.
Whence
Mary’s Obligation?
Saying
Mary did something wrong and explaining why
it was wrong are two entirely different matters. Mary had
no special obligation to the child. She was
not the child’s parent. She did not agree to take care of it. So
the infant didn’t
seem to have a right against Mary that she should feed it. We
are in agreement with Wagner on these points and that they don’t
seem relevant.
We
are in substantial agreement that the mode of killing also
doesn’t
seem relevant. I would disagree about the severity of letting the
infant starve vs. slitting it’s throat. I
have grave reservations about whether
there is a significant moral difference between killing and letting
die, so I would not necessarily agree that slitting the infant’s
throat would actually be worse. In fact, I would contend that if Mary
refuses
to feed the child, she may as well slit its throat. That, at least,
would be more merciful. But
at this point of the discussion, the distinction, if
any,
does not make a difference.
Particularly
when it comes to the “formula” case, there is
another
factor
Wagner
does not mention but we
can
be
fairly certain he would agree is not morally relevant. That factor is
Mary’s sex. In the “formula” case, if we switched Mary out and
put Peter in her place, I think we would agree Peter would have
also
been
obligated to feed the infant.
Wagner
proposes three facts
about
this case that may help us explain why Mary is obligated to feed the
child:
Mary
was
the only one directly
available.
Mary could help.
Only
basic physical needs were
required.
Again,
we are in substantial agreement that if we changed any one of these
facts, Mary’s obligation was
less certain. If Mary wasn’t the only one available, it isn’t
clear what her specific obligation would be.
If
for some reason Mary was
unable to help, her obligation certainly would
not be
clear.
I
agree with Wagner’s statement that, had
the child’s needs gone beyond basic
physical necessities, then Mary’s obligations would
have been less
clear. But for reasons that will be made clear below, I’m not sure
he agrees with that statement.
I would add a fourth fact about the “formula” case that helps
explain why Mary is obligated to feed the child:
Given the circumstances, feeding the child was not a significant
imposition.
This is the part where we are going to have controversy with Wagner.
But strictly considering the “formula” case, that feeding the
child was not a significant imposition is surely part of the reason
we think Mary did something wrong. If you see someone drowning and
there is an available rope, you would be morally criticized for not
throwing him a line. But unless you are a trained and practicing
lifeguard, you are not obligated to jump in after him. This is why if
you do, you would be regarded as a hero. Again, if you stop at a
convenience store on your way to work, and you see someone slip, you
would be morally criticized if you did not at least call the
paramedics if she is injured. But you are not obligated to drop
everything and take her to the hospital yourself. This is why if you
do, you would be regarded as a good Samaritan. And if throwing the
line or checking on the person itself imposes a significant
imposition, even the moral criticism is muted.
In Mary’s case, she was not going anywhere, whether because she
couldn’t or she chose not to. Even though she retained the right to
escape had the opportunity arose, feeding the infant in the modified
“formula” case probably would not have detracted from her ability
to escape. She was going to have to eat herself anyway. For at least
six weeks, she had nothing but time. Finally and perhaps crucially,
in this case, the supplies were already provided.
There didn’t seem to be any good reason not to feed the infant, and
this surely contributes to our sense Mary did something wrong by
allowing the child to starve.
Assessing the factors that make us think Mary did something wrong
doesn’t actually explain why we think she was wrong. But these
facts can help us to build a theory that would explain the why.
Wagner proposes the concept of the de facto guardian (DFG) to
explain facts 1-3. This concept is not to be confused with the legal
concept of de facto guardianship as it exists in some
jurisdictions, though if Wagner’s concept holds and is legally
implemented, it would replace the legal concept as it now exists.
These are the essentials of DFG:
If for any reason one finds themselves in a situation that a child
needs care, and that person is the only one available to help, that
person has “the same obligations of a parent or guardian”
(italics Wagner’s).
The person’s lack of consent to care for the child is irrelevant.
Only a threat to the person’s life can potentially change the
obligation.
Wagner is unclear whether the time period involved is relevant in
determining the scope of the obligation. Certainly the six week
period of Mary’s case is covered, which seems fairly reasonable.
Wagner asserts without argument that a de facto guardian’s
obligation covers Mary’s case even if she were stuck in the cabin
for two years. He never explicitly states exactly how long the period
the DFG obligation lasts. But given his contention that only a
threat to the person’s life may change the obligation, the time
period could last until the infant has grown into an adult without
contradicting Wagner’s theory.
This would seem to go far beyond what our intuition tells us about
this case. Six weeks given that Mary wasn’t going anywhere and
couldn’t fulfill whatever other obligations she may had anyway?
Sure. Two years? Possibly it can be stretched that long, but
crucially Wagner would have to make an actual argument, not simply
assert it. Eighteen years? Unless Mary had done something wrong
commensurate to that level of obligation, there is just no way to
justify that.
Moreover, if only a threat to the person’s life may
potentially change the obligation, then the DFG obligation is
actually greater than the actual parent’s obligations. For example,
a parent is not obligated to give blood to their children, even
though a simple blood transfusion hardly constitutes a threat to most people's lives.
In Mary’s specific case, the stipulation that only a threat to the
person’s life can potentially change the obligation conflicts with
the fact Mary would have been justified in leaving the cabin in the
original scenario and doing anything that would have allowed her to
escape should the opportunity arise in the modified scenario, even at
the risk that the child will die. DFG would suggest that it would be
impermissible to take that risk. But this would also contradict the
premise the de facto guardian has the same obligations as a
parent, since, as we shall see, even if Mary were the infant’s
parent, she would still be justified in leaving the cabin or doing
anything that would allow her to escape.
Also, if the de facto guardian has the same obligations
as a parent, then the obligation extends beyond mere physical needs.
In the “formula” case, we may be agreed Mary should have fed the
child, but even Wagner himself did not say Mary had to show infant
affection, play with it, and so on. But this is arguably part of a
parent’s obligations, which are not solely limited to providing for
its physical needs. Parenting also involves training the child to be
a functioning member of society. If Mary was indeed stuck in the
cabin for two years, does her obligation extend to potty training the
child? What about teaching it to walk and talk? DFG would suggest
that Mary’s obligation does extend this far. But this probably goes
far beyond what our intuition tells us about this case.
Finally, DFG potentially places anyone who has a random encounter
with a child under (at least) the same obligations of a parent. This
raises the question of why we would assign the position of parent to
anyone at all. Being a parent means having special obligations
towards specific children. If DFG holds, every adult has those
otherwise special obligations to every child. Whence parenting then?
However, let’s assume for the time being that Wagner’s de
facto guardian can be fixed so that it can account for Mary’s
obligation to feed the child without posing these problems. We can
rightly ask whether this is the only theory that would account for
our intuition that Mary should have fed the child. And as it so
happens, not only is there at least one other theory, it was proposed
by Thomson herself. Her concept of the Minimally Decent Samaritan
(MDS) has the potential to explain Mary’s case at least as well as
the de facto guardian concept.
Thomson’s Minimally Decent Samaritan concept proposes that if it
would be morally indecent to not help a person in need, we are
obligated to help that person. This is true even if, strictly
speaking, that person does not have a right to your assistance.
However, the scope of that obligation is limited, both in terms of
severity and time. MDS does not apply when assisting another person
requires significant sacrifices of your total well-being. MDS also
does not apply when the assistance would require a large sacrifice of
time.
Now that we have an alternative theory, we can now ask which theory
better explains Mary’s case. Here we see that MDS has far more
explanatory power than DFG. Both MDS and DFG can explain why the fact
Mary was the only one available is relevant and explain why her
obligation would have been less apparent if there are many people.
Both would also explain why Mary’s ability or lack thereof is a
factor.
When we turn to the consideration that only physical needs are
required, MDS can explain why we need only concern ourselves with
physical needs that can be readily met. Training a child to be a
functioning member of society involves a significant amount of time
and resources and includes sacrificing many other interests and
concerns. In Mary’s specific case, the time and resources spent on
training a child to be a functioning member of society would have
detracted from trying to escape if she could. As we’ve already
seen, DFG as presented by Wagner is unclear whether whether the
obligation is limited to physical needs that can be readily met and
would even suggest those obligations take precedence over Mary’s
interest in escaping.
Finally, MDS explains why the fact that feeding the child would not
have been a significant imposition plays a role in our sense that
Mary should have fed the infant, while also explaining why our sense
that the obligation becomes less clear the more significant the
imposition becomes. If the formula weren’t already supplied, or if
preparing the formula required a long arduous process, or if feeding
the child would in fact detract from her ability to escape, or if we
were talking about eighteen years, or given any number of possible
ifs, our sense of Mary’s obligation becomes less clear, and MDS can
explain that.
In contrast, DFG says no imposition short of the threat of death can
release Mary. Wagner in effect is saying that our sense that the
severity of the imposition (short of death) has a role to play in our
judgment is simply wrong; we have to bite the bullet here. However,
Wagner gives us no reason to believe we should bite this
bullet, let alone that we must do so. We are expected to bite
the bullet simply on his say so. Perhaps he is right. If so, that
still requires an argument.
Minimally Decent Samaritanism can also explain cases where our
intuition says someone has done something wrong that the de facto
guardian can’t explain.
We’ve already experimented with exchanging Mary for Peter and
concluded Mary’s sex is not relevant to our sense of outrage. What
happens if we exchange the infant for an adult who is disabled in
such a way they cannot feed themselves? I’d imagine we would still
feel morally outraged, that Mary should not have let this person
starve. This would suggest the infant’s age or stage of development
is not in itself a relevant factor.
With its specialized concern for children, DFG to this point does not
explain why Mary would be obligated to feed the disabled adult. MDS
can explain this.
Let’s look at some other cases, drawn from both this essay and
Thomson’s “Defense.”
MDS explains why we can be morally criticized for not throwing an
available line to a drowning person. DFG would only explain it if
the drowning person were a child.
MDS explains why should call the paramedics if we someone slip and
seriously injure themselves. DFG would only explain it if the
injured person were a child.
MDS explains why we ought to allow Thomson’s violinist to stay
plugged into you if doing so only requires an hour and does not
threaten your health. DFG would only explain it if the violinist
were a child.
MDS explains why Henry Fonda should briefly touch Thomson’s brow
to save her life if he need only walk across the room. DFG would
only explain it if Thomson were a child.
If the legend surrounding the Kitty Genovese case were true, MDS
would explain why someone should have called the police.
DFG would only explain it if Genovese were a child.
Given the greater explanatory power of MDS, we conclude that it is a
better explanation for Mary’s case than DFG. As we turn to examine
the “no formula” case, we would be justified in using MDS as the
primary theory to judge whether Mary’s obligation extends to
breastfeeding the infant. But just in case DFG can be fixed, we will
also look at this case through the first premise of the theory, that
the de facto guardian has the same obligations as a parent.
The
“No Formula” Case
We rejected the conclusion Mary was obligated to feed the infant in
the initial story Wagner proposed and offered a good justification
for that rejection. But if the story is properly modified, we can
agree that Mary did something wrong by letting the child starve. We
also found substantial though not perfect agreement about the facts
that make us think Mary was wrong to let the infant starve. We then
considered Wagner’s de facto guardian theory and found it
lacking, especially in comparison to Thomson’s Minimally Decent
Samaritanism. We have, however, agreed to consider the premise that
Mary has the same obligations toward the strange child as she would
have toward her own child for the sake of argument.
Wagner may not be entirely happy with this, but presumably there is
still enough here for him to move on to the next step of his
strategy. After all, the bottom line is that we are agreed that Mary
was obligated to feed the infant in the “formula” case.
Now, Wagner asks us to consider a modification to his scenario (or
the scenario as modified to create Mary’s obligation in the
“formula” case). Suppose the kidnappers did not provide any
formula. But remember, she gave birth a week ago and is lactating.
So she could breastfeed the infant. Now the question before us is
this: Does Mary’s obligation in the “formula” case still hold
if the only way to feed the child is breastfeeding?
Obviously, Wagner takes it as a given that it does.
Just as obviously, Wagner anticipates that those who agree with him
in the “formula” case won’t necessarily go along with him in
the “no formula” case. He devoted only two paragraphs to the
“formula” case but takes four to comment the “no formula”
case. His language becomes less certain in section Ic: “If you
think she did not have a moral obligation … If you have the same
intuition I have.” Wagner clearly knows he’s moved into more
controversial territory.
The “no formula” case looks sufficiently enough like Thomson’s
strung-up violinist we could simply assert the right to refuse
applies and be done with it. Most of the disanalogies between the
strung-up violinist and a pregnant person Wagner will go on to
propose, even if we were to grant they are relevant, simply do not
apply in Mary’s case. We will consider the remaining disanalogies
that may have relevance to Mary’s case soon enough. First, we will
consider a new distinction Wagner proposes.
Strangely enough, Wagner waits until section VIc point E to even try
making an argument that Mary’s case is not like the strung-up
violinist. In Mary’s case, she is in the position of a de facto
guardian, whereas you are not in the position of a de facto
guardian in the original scenario proposed by Thomson. This
argument clearly depends on DFG being correct, but as we’ve already
seen, it is very problematic at best. Even if we were hold on to the
premise that a de facto guardian has the same obligations as a
parent, that still leaves us with the question of whether those
obligations extend to the direct use of of one’s body.
Parents do not have the obligation to give their children blood,
tissue, or organs, even if it is necessary for the child to live. It
stands to reason that this would include breast milk. So if Mary has
the same obligations as a parent in this case, she then does not need
to breastfeed the child. The right to refuse still applies.
Wagner here argues that a difference between Mary’s case and the
violinist is that the infant needs food whereas the violinist needs
medical care. Wagner asks us to shift the location of the violinist
scenario a deserted hospital that has plenty of food available. Now,
Wagner says you are in a position of a de facto guardian, even
though that requires shifting the goalposts so that DFG applies to
disabled people as well as children. This is starting to look ad
hoc, but we’ll bear with him a little while longer.
Before going on, let’s note that shifting the location to a
deserted hospital makes the case look like the original, unmodified
scenario. We’ve already established in this original scenario that
Mary was entirely justified in leaving. By parity of reasoning you
are equally justified in leaving the deserted hospital. So now we
have to modify the scenario (again) to get to where we can start
saying you and Mary have an obligation to feed the violinist and the
infant. So when we get to the “no formula” case, we just wind up
in the same position. You can unhook yourself and Mary doesn’t have
to breastfeed.
Not so, Wagner asserts, because the difference between medical
treatment and feeding and sheltering are such that in the deserted
hospital case, you can still unhook yourself: “In this case, you
are obligated (morally/legally) to feed and shelter the violinist,
but you are not obligated (morally/legally) to give him your body as
medical care.” So you can unhook yourself from the violinist but
you still have to feed him. Even though he’ll die if you unhook him
and therefore he will not need to be fed. Okay. Wagner will have to
pardon us if we are confused.
Never mind, though. Even if the application leads to a weird effect,
the point itself is clear. The problem is that Wagner does not give
us a reason to believe this is a distinction that makes a difference.
Supposing parents to have an obligation to feed their children even
if that means the direct use of their bodies, we have only reversed
the problem. If parents are obligated to feed their children using
their bodies, it still stands to reason they are obligated to use
their blood, tissue and organs for their children’s medical care as
well. Why? Because parents are obligated to provide their
children medical care. To say they have to let their bodies be used
for food but not medical care is completely arbitrary.
Now let’s turn to the disanalogies between the strung-up violinist
and a pregnant person that may have relevance to Mary’s case. In
section Vb point B, Wagner discusses the point that kidneys weren’t
intended to filter other people’s blood while uteruses are intended
to gestate prenates. One could argue a similar difference exists
between Mary’s case and Thomson’s violinist in that breast milk
is intended to feed infants.
Wagner is suitably cautious about using an argument like this. He
points out that accepting this difference has moral relevance
requires certain worldviews and would likely be rejected by those who
don’t share those commitments. He later acknowledges making this
kind of argument into a moral argument is difficult. Nevertheless, he
holds this disnalogy should not be rejected just because it is
controversial; it could still be useful to those who share their
worldview.
However, I am inclined to accept the premises “the purpose of
uteruses is to gestate prenates” and “the purpose of breast milk
is to feed infants” are true.
What I take issue with is the implied conclusions: Mary is required
to breastfeed and pregnant people are required to bring their
pregnancies to term. Wagner is correct to acknowledge this argument
is hard to make. I’m going to demonstrate exactly why it is so
difficult.
Imagine, if you will, a person with a penis rapes a person with a
vagina. The rapist is caught and put on trial. The rapist now offers
this argument for their defense: “Ladies and gentlemen of the jury:
the purpose of a vagina is sexual intercourse. Therefore, the
‘victim’ is obligated to allow me to have sex with them.”
Except for psychopathic rapists, I would imagine everyone will think
this defense is absurd.
This is the problem facing those who would make a teleological
argument that Mary is required to breastfeed or pregnant people are
required to gestate. The conclusion does not follow from the premise,
so the argument itself is invalid. I can accept that the fact breast
milk is for feeding infants or that uteruses are for gestating
prenates may possibly be a necessary condition for requiring
Mary to breastfeed or pregnant people to gestate, but it is not a
sufficient one. Unless someone can successfully argue that people
with vaginas are not obligated to sleep with every person with a
penis that comes along, but that a lactating person does have to
breastfeed any and every hungry infant and a person with a uterus has
to gestate every prenate that lands in it, the teleological argument
fails.
In section VIIc, Wagner proposes we change the scenario so that Mary
signed a consent form to participate in the behavior psychologists’
experiment. The fact that she found herself in care of an infant was
due to pure random chance. This would raise all sorts of questions on
its own, but never mind. Surely now Mary would be obligated to
breastfeed the infant, even apart from DFG (or MDS) considerations!
And yes, we’ll agree to that—for as long as Mary consented to
participate in the experiment.
Wagner forgot that agreeing to be part of such experiments comes with
the right to stop participating at any time for any reason. If Mary
decided to discontinue her participation in the experiment, the
psychologists would have been obligated to release her.
If the psychologists failed to release her, Mary acquired the right
to escape. The rest of the scenario flows accordingly.
While Minimally Decent Samaritanism would likely apply in the
“formula” case, it certainly would not apply in the “no
formula” case. If Mary were simply able to call the police, and
they said they would be able to get to her the next morning, MDS
would almost certainly apply.
If the police said it would take six weeks to get to her, it becomes
less certain MDS applies, but given the fact she did have the
assurance she would be rescued, it could be argued that the six week
period falls within it. If she started having problems breastfeeding,
such as developing mastitis, MDS would certainly no longer apply.
But this is not the situation we are presented with. Mary had no
assurance she will be freed except the word of her kidnappers. The
“no formula” case, if anything, has even more ominous
implications than the original. Mary would still have the right to do
anything that would allow her to escape if she could. If she
breastfeeds the child, her body will continue to produce milk, which
means the calories she consumes are not going into anything that may
help her escape had the opportunity arisen. And for all Mary knows,
she was going to need those resources. Minimally Decent Samaritanism
does not apply to this case.
We have saved considering what might change if the infant Mary
discovered was her own for last. If we were outraged on our first
reading of the original story, we can imagine the outrage would be
even more intense if the child were in fact Mary’s. Given that
Wagner’s arguments have failed so far, supposing it was Mary’s
infant could serve as his Hail Mary pass. So go back to the original
story. We are outraged that Mary let the infant starve. When we learn
it was Mary’s own child, our sense of outrage doubles.
But when we calm down and start thinking rationally, we should ask
whether anything meaningful has changed. Mary no longer had to figure
out what happened to her child, but in every other respect, nothing
has changed. Mary still had no assurance they would be freed. People
trying to find her still would not have known where to look. She
would have still been justified in leaving. It would still would have
been imprudent to take the infant. And even if leaving meant risking
the child will die, for all Mary knew, both were going to die anyway,
so her child would have been no worse off if her escape attempt
failed. The rest of our argument flows accordingly.
Differences
in Our Intuition?
Assuming, as Wagner does in section IVb, our intuitions are different
in the violinist and “no formula” cabin stories,
what can explain this? Let’s try playing around with the scenarios
and see what we discover.
First, let’s have Mary and you switch places. So now, it is Mary
that is hooked into the violinist and you are stuck in the cabin. It
doesn’t seem like this will change intuitions much, if at all.
Wagner would still presumably think that Mary can be unhooked while
you would have to breastfeed the infant (assuming of course, that you
can). So it seems that this is not a case of sheer hypocrisy.
Just to be absolutely certain this is not about one’s biological
sex,
let’s take you out and insert Peter back into the cabin. Again,
Wagner would still presumably think Peter would have to breastfeed
the infant assuming he could. So it also seems this is not a case of
sheer sexism. We can probably say the intuition has nothing to do
with who is providing the service.
So let’s switch the violinist and the infant. Now, you are hooked
into the infant while Mary is faced with breastfeeding the
violinist.
For the violinist, I think we would have much the same reaction as in
the “no formula” case. If there is still a sense of outrage, it
probably wouldn’t be as intense as in the case of the infant (see
note 6). But if you are hooked up to the infant, I suspect Wagner
would now argue you are required to remain attached.
I suspect that even some of us might hesitate to say we can demand
detachment.
It seems the difference in our intuition for these cases is that we
are talking about the fate of a child. This is understandable. We are
socially and/or biologically conditioned to regard the death of a
child as especially tragic. While we certainly do not want to dismiss
that feeling out of hand, if we think about it rationally, we would
realize the fact an infant is the one in need of help has no moral
relevance to whether we have the right to refuse.
Some of us would argue that the infant is not a person with the right
to life, and that is reason enough to show Mary has no obligation in
the “no formula” case (and probably the “formula” case as
well). However, this contention is itself highly controversial.
Even if I were inclined to agree, I don’t think we can or should
rest our case there (see note 8). This means even if we don’t think
the infant is a person, we should stipulate it for the purpose of
discussion.
Instead, I propose we ask ourselves what would be necessary to
rationally justify requiring Mary to breastfeed the infant or us to
remain attached to the infant. It would require arguing that children
have a special right to people’s bodies if they need those bodies
to live. In other words, we would have to argue that children have a
higher right to life than the violinist. Or me. Or you. Or Wagner.
Even if I were able to make such an argument, I’m not willing to go
there. I don’t think we as a people are willing to go there either.
Even Wagner himself doesn’t seem willing to go there explicitly,
which is why he shifted the goalposts to include the violinist under
DFG in the deserted hospital case. So, insofar as there is an
intuition that Mary is obligated to breastfeed the infant, we should
bite the bullet and allow that Mary had the right to refuse.
We are justified at this point in saying we have defeated Wagner’s
argument that Mary was obligated to breastfeed the infant in the “no
formula” case.
With that defeat, the rest of Wagner’s strategy falls. We need not
consider changing the scenario to consider something even closer to
pregnancy. Beyond the “no formula” case, Wagner is simply
demonstrating that his cruelty knows no bounds.
However, we do have one final point to make.
Legal
Intuitions?
In a properly modified scenario, we found some agreement with Wagner
that Mary should have fed the infant in the “no formula” case.
Suppose Mary had no justification or excuse for letting the child
starve in that case; she simply refused to do it out of cold-hearted
indifference. Now further suppose our outrage was such that we
declared, “There ought to be a law against that!”
Do we need DFG, assuming it could be fixed? Again, the answer is no.
We already have a law that could cover that kind of situation:
depraved-indifference
homicide. Typically such cases involve extreme recklessness with
gross indifference to human life. However, with suitable precautions
so people’s basic rights are not violated, the
depraved-indifference homicide doctrine could be adapted to Mary’s
simple refusal to feed the infant along with, for example, not
throwing an available line to a drowning person.
Conclusion
Wagner’s
argument fails in nearly every way imaginable. His initial story is
not the slam dunk he thinks it is. His de
facto guardian theory as
presented is problematic,
perhaps beyond the point of repair, while Thomson’s Minimally
Decent Samaritanism explains our sense in the “formula” case
equally well if not better. His DFG theory requires us to bite a
bullet that Thomson’s MDS
doesn’t, and we are just supposed to accept
that. When it comes to the “no formula” case, Wagner expects us
to just accept there is a difference between feeding and medical care
even though the distinction won’t stand under his own theory. His
variation on the Responsibility Objection is so abysmally bad that
the Responsibility Objection has become self-refuted. His
argument can’t be saved even if we assumed the infant was Mary’s
child. Wagner simply can’t show Mary was
required to breastfeed the infant in his scenario. Insofar as this
scenario is supposed to represent pregnancy resulting from rape, we
must conclude that people who were raped are not obligated to carry
any resulting pregnancy.
Remember,
this is one of the best versions of this type of argument available.
Lesser versions of this argument, whether we are discussing deserted
islands, snowed-in cabins, stowaways on ships, wandering
toddlers, or whatever else
fail just as badly. No one has the right to use a person’s body
without consent. The sooner
the slavers realize this, the better off we’ll all be.