I'm
tired of “defending” abortion. By this I mean abortion is often
treated as something that must be defended rather than a positive
right. This is implied by the title of Judith Jarvis Thomson's “A Defense of Abortion”
and David Boonin's book-length treatment under the same title.1
Boonin's Defense
in particular is a systematic treatment of various arguments posed by
abortion critics. Most of the literature I've read (though admittedly
my reading is hardly comprehensive) favoring abortion rights is cast
as a defense against abortion critics. Such a “defense” basically
implies an argument that runs along the following lines:
1. Abortion is
permissible only if no valid objections are raised against it.
2. No valid
objection has been raised against abortion.
3. Therefore
abortion is permissible.
We
would never argue for the freedom of expression or freedom of
religion in this manner. We press positive cases that speaking freely
or going to church is permissible, defending against objections only
secondarily.2
Yet, so far in my admittedly non-comprehensive reading, I've found
only two works that attempt to establish a positive case for abortion
rights: Roderick T. Long's “Abortion, Abandonment, and Positive Rights: The Limits of Compulsory Altruism”
(and note the term limits
in the title) and Katha Pollitt's Pro:
Reclaiming Abortion Rights.
Why
should this matter? A “defense” of abortion focuses on arguing
“on terms that critics of abortion can, and already do, accept.”3
This is a perfectly valid approach. If you can't defend a stance on
your own terms, why should I accept that stance? If the goal is to
avoid a standstill, then this approach is probably the best way to
proceed.
But,
like the debate about biblical inerrancy,
I think that debating abortion will always result in a standstill.
Abortion
opponents
will either engage in new levels of sophistry
or simply eschew reason and say intuition is the only thing that really matters.4
Abortion opponents, like biblical inerrantists, will always find some
escape hatch, so the only point in debating them is to benefit third
parties still amendable to argument.
If
our goal is to benefit interested but uncommitted third parties, then
presenting arguments an abortion critic is likely to reject has its
place. For example, a third party benefits from having differing
accounts of what it means to be a person with the right to life and
whether those criteria apply to prenates. Even if this leaves those
debating abortion at a standstill, the third party will have clear
choices and an idea of the rationale behind the differing arguments.
As
it so happens, the argument I am going to make here starts with
premises that are generally accepted by the abortion rights
proponent, the abortion critic, and the undecided person alike. From
those premises, I will derive a principle which I believe soundly
unifies those premises. Finally, I will demonstrate that if we
consistently apply that principle to the topic of abortion, we will
conclude abortion is permissible.
But
first, we need to get some of the preliminary issues out of the way.
The
Preliminary Issues and Fine Print
Prenatal
personhood:
I am neutral about
whether a prenate is a person with the same right to life as you and
me. Personally, I am inclined to believe that humans cannot possibly
acquire personhood at least until monozygotic twinning
and tetragametic chimerism
are no longer possible, and probably do not acquire it until birth.
Between these two points, I am open to the possibility, merely
considering it doubtful. So far, I have not found any arguments
favoring prenatal personhood convincing, though I think there are
some promising approaches
that may yet be parleyed into a successful argument.
In
view of my neutrality, my arguments favoring abortion rights
stipulate prenatal personhood. Some abortion rights advocates may
think this cedes too much to the abortion opponent, particularly
since I don't really believe the prenate is a person. However,
Thomson's “Defense” long ago established that it is not enough to
show that the prenate is a person with the right to life, the
abortion critic must also show that an abortion unjustly deprives the
prenate of its life. Abortion opponents have generally accepted that
part of her argument, effectively rendering prenatal personhood
irrelevant to the abortion debate.
Moreover,
I have found time and again that
abortion critics
do not consistently apply the same rules that apply to you and me to
the prenate. In other words, what they try to do is give the prenate
special rights that exempt them from those rules.5
I've hinted at this in my objections to the so-called responsibility argument,
and I may write future posts highlighting those inconsistencies. If
stipulating prenatal personhood cedes ground to the abortion critic,
it is not a concession that does them any favors.
Meanwhile,
stipulating prenatal personhood also allows me to save space. I need
not repeatedly say things like “if the prenate is a person” or
“the prenate's rights, if any.”
General
rules and exceptions:
I am making an argument that abortion is generally permissible. In
doing so, I will be making reference to rules about the general
permissibility or impermissibility of certain actions. Many, if not
most rules have exceptions, and perhaps you can think of exceptions
to the rules I appeal to. It may be that even if you grant my
argument about the general permissibility of abortion, you would
still be able think of some exceptions. If those exceptions are
justified, I will gladly grant them. However, exceptions do not void
the general rule.
Consider
this rule: “Homicide is wrong.” I would imagine you agree with
this rule. I would also imagine you would also immediately think of
exceptions to this rule. Self-defense is an exception that is
considered noncontroversial. Other exceptions, like capital
punishment and war are more controversial in modern society, but
legitimate arguments can be made in favor of these exceptions.
However, I think we would agree that even granting the exceptions,
homicide is still generally wrong.
Likewise,
the general permissibility of abortion does not mean there are
specific cases where a woman having an abortion is not legitimately
subject to moral criticism. I myself have read accounts that I found
morally disturbing. I suspect that many of you have read or heard
accounts you found disturbing, even if you tend to favor abortion
rights. I am not saying that every woman's decision to have an
abortion is above moral criticism; I am saying that she is permitted
to make that decision.6
Again,
this discussion allows me to save space. I will make statements that
on its face do not allow exceptions. When I say “X is wrong” or
“Y is permissible,” I generally intend those statements to be
understood as “X is generally wrong” or “Y is permissible in
typical cases.”
With
these thoughts in mind, let us proceed.
The
Argument7
Consider
the following propositions:
1.
Raping
someone
is wrong.
2.
Enslaving
someone
is wrong.
3.
Kidnapping someone for ransom or to further a criminal purpose is
wrong.
4.
Subjecting someone to
involuntary medical/scientific experimentation is wrong.
5. Forcing someone to donate blood, tissue,
and/or organs is wrong.
I
think few, if any, people will have major objections to these
propositions. We may quibble over the precise meaning of rape,
slavery, and kidnapping, but if there are actions that are
universally wrong, we would be agreed these actions would be among
them. As for involuntary medical/scientific experimentation, Joseph Mengele and the Tuskegee syphilis experiment are
widely if not universally reviled.
While
debating abortion, I have encountered a few people who are open to
forced organ donation--to a point. None openly advocate the practice.
The vast majority of abortion critics agree that forcing bodily
donations is wrong. Legally, such a practice has been forbidden by the courts in the
United States. Meanwhile, China's practice of executing prisoners to harvest organs
is roundly condemned by the international community. I think it is
safe to say that proposition 5 is generally regarded as sound.
Now
let us consider these propositions:
6. One may do anything necessary to prevent or
escape being subjected to the actions of propositions 1 through 5.
7. Moreover, third parties may also do anything
necessary to aid someone prevent or escape being subjected to the
actions of propositions 1 through 5.
Again,
I don't think many people will pose serious objections to these
propositions. The law already recognizes them in cases of rape and
kidnapping. Surely anyone trying to take another person's organs or
perform involuntary medical experiments on them poses enough
a threat of serious bodily harm that
self-defense would be justified.8
And surely no one would condemn someone (legally or morally) for
killing a slavemaster or Mengele if that is was necessary to escape
them.
Now
let us consider why the actions in propositions 1-5 are wrong, so
wrong that it would justify doing anything necessary to prevent
or escape those actions. At first glance, propositions 1-5 are just a
random list of acts. They are serious wrongs, to be sure—serious
enough to make propositions 6-7 true. Do these acts have something
else in common?
Yes.
All these acts involve using someone's body without consent. The
difference between rape and having sex is that both parties consent
to the latter. The difference between a slave and an employee is that
the employee can quit. Kidnapping involves holding someone against
their will, typically to force a third party into doing something to
get their loved one returned. Involuntary medical/scientific
experimentation uses a persons body for an end the person does not
know and may not care about. And forcing someone to donate blood,
tissue, or organs takes something from someone's very body for
another's use.
The
common factor of using someone's body without consent also explains
why these acts are serious enough to make propositions 6-7 true, even
if these acts do not physically injure the person. One's body is as
close to an absolutely inviolable boundary as it gets. One's body is
perhaps the only thing that everyone can truly call their own. To use
someone's body without consent is thus a most profound violation of
the person.
We
can now connect propositions 1-5 together with this proposition:
8. Using someone's body without consent is
wrong.
And
we can accordingly modify propositions 6-7 as well:
9. One may do anything necessary to prevent or
escape another using their body without consent.
10. Moreover, third parties may also do
anything necessary to aid someone prevent or escape having their
bodies used without consent.
Now,
let us turn to the subject of pregnancy. Consider the following
proposition:
11. During pregnancy, a prenate uses the
mother's body.
Proposition 11 is simply a fact. Even if there
were no other considerations, these are some of the things prenates
do to women:
They implant themselves into the woman's body. They dampen the
woman's immune system. They tap the woman's blood supply to obtain
nutrients and oxygen. They alter the woman's brain chemistry. They
build their bones by taking the calcium from the woman's bones and
teeth. They release their wastes back into her body.
When
the woman wants to have a baby, she allows the prenate do this to
her. In this case, the prenate is doing nothing wrong. When the woman
doesn't want to have a baby, what the prenate does to her causes her
great harm. Based on proposition 8, we would conclude the prenate is
doing something wrong. We'll summarize thus:
12. During an unwanted pregnancy, a prenate is
using the mother's body without consent.
13. A
prenate's use of the mother's body without consent is wrong.
And based on propositions 9-10, we conclude that the mother or a
third party may do anything necessary to escape the prenate's use of
the mother's body without consent:
14. The mother
may do anything necessary to end the prenate's nonconsensual use of
her body.
15. Moreover,
a third party may also do anything necessary to aid a woman escape
the prenate's nonconsensual use of her body.
All
that remains to be asked is whether an abortion is necessary to
escape the prenate's nonconsensual use
of the woman's body. We can agree that
one can do anything necessary to escape the situations described in
propositions 1-5. Even so, killing the person doing these things
isn't always necessary. We would only say that killing the offender
is justified if killing them were the last resort or if killing them
was the only means of escape. Surely this applies to the prenate
using its mother's body without consent as well. However, given
current technology, an abortion is the only
means to escape a prenate using the mother's body without consent.
Should the technology develop where the prenate can be transferred to
another person or an artificial womb without any further cost9
to the woman than an abortion, the necessity of abortion would be
questionable. Meanwhile, at least during the early stages of
pregnancy, the answer is undoubtedly positive.
Another
thing that might make the necessity of an abortion questionable is
whether the fetus is viable. When the fetus has become viable, it
could be argued that an abortion is no longer necessary. One can
either induce labor or have a Caesarean
section to
end the unwanted pregnancy. Here, I must admit I am not a medical
expert and therefore cannot answer this objection definitively. I can
note that inducing labor or having a C-section both involve
significant negative costs to the mother in terms of her total
well-being. How do those costs stack against the negative costs of
having a late-term abortion? That is a question I will leave to the
experts.
However,
when we say killing the offender would be justified if killing them
were the last resort, we generally do not mean this in an absolute
sense. We don't generally require people to take heroic measures to
avoid killing those subjecting us to the actions of propositions 1-5.
We don't, for example, require people to put themselves into further
danger before saying
that
killing the rapist or kidnapper the last resort. One may do so, which
is why we would consider such people heroic, but they are not required
to do so. We may say then that insofar as a late-term abortion is
less risky than inducing labor or having a C-section, the late-term
abortion can be considered the
last resort.
We
also probably wouldn't require people to incur significant costs to
themselves to avoid killing the rapist or slavemaster, even if we
aren't strictly talking about physical risk. The question is how much
cost one must incur before we can say
that
killing the offender was
the
last resort. It seems to me that this can only be decided on a
case-by-case basis. I would suggest using something like the
reasonable person standard.10
Are the costs of not killing the offender too much to ask of a
typical person? If the answer is positive, then we may affirm killing
the offender was
the last resort. If not, then killing the offender would not be
justified. I suspect mere inconvenience would not qualify. If all a
slave has to do to escape is wait an hour for the master to fall
asleep before sneaking away, then killing the slavemaster would not
likely be justified. Similarly, if the only consideration were that a
late-term abortion is faster than the process of inducing labor or
having a C-section, then a late-term abortion would not likely be
justified. On the other hand, if escaping without killing the
offender involves a good deal of pain and suffering, that would
qualify. If the choice was between being raped, undergoing torture to
avoid killing the rapist, and simply killing the rapist, then killing
the rapist would be justified. If the negative costs of induced
labor, a C-section, and late-term abortions are roughly equal, then
even late-term abortions are justified. And the higher the costs of
induced labor or C-sections vs. late-term abortions, the more a
late-term abortion is justified. Provisionally speaking, even a
late-term, post-viability abortion may be considered necessary for a
mother to escape the nonconsensual use of her body by the prenate.11
Let
us complete the argument then:
16. An
abortion is necessary to escape a prenate's nonconsensual use of a
woman's body.
17. Therefore
abortion is permissible.
Update 21 October 2022: I originally developed this essay through online discussion in various online forums. Interested readers are invited to examine my comment history on Disqus to peruse the development of my thinking on abortion, though I would warn you that you would have to go through nearly a decade of comments. More recently I started seeing references to Eileen L. McDonagh's Breaking the Abortion Deadlock: From Choice to Consent (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996). From the descriptions, it was clear she was making a similar argument to the one I made above. Even more recently, I obtained a copy and read it.
The arguments are astonishingly similar. Both are extensions of Thomson's argument in a sense. Both are modeled on self-defense, though I think McDonagh is more full-throttled in asserting abortion is self-defense, as opposed to like self-defense. However, this is probably a distinction that makes no real difference. I had encountered some forms of self-defense arguments in pro-choice circles, but I tended to shy away from them until I had what I thought was a new, central insight on the matter: in an unwanted pregnancy, the fetus is the aggressor. But it turns out McDonagh had that same insight nearly twenty years before I wrote this essay. McDonagh got there first; I merely came to the same place using a different route.
The only substantial difference between McDonagh and my argument is the starting position. McDonagh begins with a consideration of the legal concept of wrongful pregnancy works out from there (7). Under this view, it is the conceptus that causes pregnancy. Of course, I did note that the prenate implants itself into the pregnant person in my essay, but this was in the context of demonstrating that the prenate is in fact using the pregnant person's body. This is a distinction that does make a difference. McDonagh builds on that insight by proposing that sex be decoupled from pregnancy (Chapter 3). This has obvious implications for the Responsibility Objection. To make a long story short, consent to sex is not consent to pregnancy.
In contrast, my argument starts with a consideration what things like rape, slavery, kidnapping, etc., fundamentally are and why that makes them wrong. Under this view, it simply doesn't matter how one becomes pregnant, any more than it doesn't matter how one came to be raped, enslaved, or kidnapped. It is the fact that an unwanted pregnancy is fundamentally the same thing as rape, slavery, kidnapping, etc., and wrong for the same fundamental reason that matters. Since they are the same thing, and wrong for the same reasons, the permitted response to the unwanted pregnancy is the same and justified for the same reason. This also has obvious implications for the Responsibility Objection. To make a long story short, consent to sex is irrelevant.
4Another
approach is to fall back on one's religion, which of course raises
the question of why I should be bound by their religion when we live
in a secular society.
5It
is this fact that more than anything else convinces me that abortion
critics' real purpose is to control the lives of women, especially
their sexuality. But that is an argument for another day.
7Astute
readers will recognize the general influence of Thomson and
especially Long. I am, however, taking a different approach.
10I
would
argue that the reasonable woman standard is especially justified in
this
case. Women are the only ones who get pregnant, suffer the effects
of pregnancy, and
incur the costs of induced labor, c-sections, and late-term
abortions. This is not just a differential of effect in unwanted
interactions or a case of historical vulnerability as in sexual
harassment cases. Pregnancy is a case where men and women are
fundamentally different; men simply don't have to face an unwanted
pregnancy even in theory.
11Since
late-term abortions are
rare and are typically performed only in cases where the mother's
life or health are threatened and/or cases of fetal deformity, the
case I make here about viability may well be moot. Even if I
conceded viability as the point where abortion is no longer
necessary, I will still have made my case that abortion is
permissible in typical cases. I do not so concede because the
wrongness of using someone's body without consent does not depend on
the duration of use. I am therefore obligated to take viability into
consideration when examining the issue of whether abortion is
necessary to escape the prenate's nonconsensual use of the mother's
body.
No comments:
Post a Comment