Secular Pro-Life (SPL) announced they were going on hiatus for the week of 22-29 December 2014. It appears they have been using the time to systematically ban pro-choice advocates from commenting and deleting their comments. I noticed this today when I was going through my Disqus comments and discovered a string of them had been marked "Removed." So far, at least forty of my posts have been so removed as I write this post. I've been given no warning, no explanation. When I made another post, I was informed I had been banned from posting comments. Again, no warning, no explanation.
Going over several blog entries, I've noticed that at least eight more pro-choice commenters had at least some of their posts deleted. I can't say for certainty the posters have also been banned, but no doubt they will get a surprise when SPL publishes new blogs and they try to comment.
Don't get me wrong here. It is SPL's blog and they can allow or disallow comments from anyone they so choose. And it is certainly no skin off my back if they are so insecure about their position that they have to block opposing viewpoints being left on their blog. If they only want to hear from yes-men, that's not my problem.
What is interesting though is that SPL has posted several blogs complaining about perceived censorship when it comes from the pro-choice side. Take a look here, here, here, and here.
I guess censorship doesn't really bother them that much after all.
An occasional series of essays or notes on subjects of interest to me. Most often the topic will be religion or politics, but I'm going to write about whatever I feel like.
Sunday, December 28, 2014
Thursday, December 11, 2014
Bodily Rights vs. "The Responsibility Argument"
Lately,
I've been spending a lot of time debating the abortion issue.1
A frequently recurring theme I run into is the so-called
responsibility argument. The responsibility argument is usually used
by anti-abortion advocates in response to the bodily rights argument
put forth by pro-choice advocates. So to understand the
responsibility argument, we must first briefly review the bodily
rights argument.
The
classic statement of the bodily rights argument is Judith Jarvis
Thomson's “A Defense of Abortion.”
Thomson argued that even if a prenate was entitled to the right to
life, that right does not include a claim to using the mother's body
in order to sustain itself. Just as we have the right2
to refuse anyone our body parts, even when their lives depend on it,
so too a mother can refuse the prenate the use of her body. An
abortion is therefore permissible in most cases.
The
responsibility argument counters that, by virtue of voluntarily
engaging in an activity knowing that pregnancy is a foreseeable
result, the mother has given the prenate a claim to her body. This is
sometimes phrased as “Consent to sex is consent to pregnancy.”
Other times, it is more bluntly phrased as “[Choose a snarl word denoting woman]
opened her legs, she can pay the
price.” However phrased, the argument is that the mother's bodily
autonomy has been forfeited3
by the act of having sex. Excluding cases of rape,4
abortion is therefore impermissible. Matters such as using birth
control are irrelevant so long as the risk of pregnancy is not zero.
I
must admit the responsibility argument does make a prima
facie
case for giving the prenate a claim on its mother's body in non-rape
cases.5
The idea that people are required to take responsibility for their
actions is well established in both legal and ethical reasoning. The
consequences may sometimes include the forfeiture of certain rights,
including bodily autonomy.6
Thus, we cannot simply dismiss this argument out of hand.
The
questions that confronts us are: Is the woman really responsible for
her pregnancy in a morally meaningful way? Granting the woman has
some responsibility for her condition, does that responsibility rise
to the level that abortion becomes impermissible when the woman had
voluntary sex?
I
have already gone through many outlines and started many drafts of
this post. But the more I think about the “responsibility
argument,” the more objections I come up with. So I've decided
that, rather than write an essay that connects all my objections
together, I would just make a numbered list. I am not
saying these arguments are equally strong, though I do think some of
them are decisive.
Without
further ado then--
1.
Consent to sex may be voluntary, but it is not necessarily free. To
understand what I mean here, consider something more than ninety-nine
per cent of adults have done at one time or another: getting up in
the morning, crawling into their vehicles, and going to a crappy job,
working for a crappy employer, making crappy wages. Those actions are
completely voluntary—nobody put a gun to their heads and said
they must
do this. Yet, for all that, are those actions really free? No, they
did it not because they wanted to, but because there is a host of
pressures and obligations that forced them to do so. To not go to
those crappy jobs carried consequences that made having even a crappy
job worthwhile. Likewise with consenting to sex. Often enough, a
woman consents to sex because of pressures and obligations7
that force her to do so.
Why
does this matter when it comes to the “responsibility argument?”
Precisely because of the rape exception. The rape exception
specifically excludes rape victims because she was forced into the
act. If being forced into the act is enough to exempt women from a
general prohibition against abortion, then we can't limit ourselves
to considering the crime of rape. We need to also exempt those who
were forced to have sex by means other than physical force.
2.
Sex may be necessary,8
but it is not sufficient to cause pregnancy. In order to get
pregnant, a number of different factors must be in place, most of
which are beyond the woman's control. The woman had sex, what happens
after that is under the control of nature. The woman's lack of
control over whether conception occurs or not also casts doubt
whether pregnancy is foreseeable for any given act of intercourse.
3.
Granting that objection 2 is wrong, it is still nature's fault that
the prenate needs the woman's body to survive. In human reproduction,
there simply isn't an option where the prenate can be created and not
require the woman's body to survive. The woman is no more responsible
for the prenate's condition than a potential organ donor is
responsible for the illness or injury that caused the need for a
replacement organ. In other words, at most she is simply responsible
for the fact the prenate exists, and not for the fact it needs her
body to survive.
4.
Accepting a risk does not entail that we must accept the result
should the worst occur. When we get into our vehicles and start the
engine, we accept that there is a risk we will be injured in a car
accident. But should an accident occur, it would be absurd to say
that we must therefore forego medical treatment.
5.
Nor does accepting a risk entail that we automatically
give up our rights. If I leave my door unlocked in the knowledge that
there are burglars out there, it would be absurd to say I've
forfeited my property rights should a burglar actually enter my home
and steal my things. If this is true for mere property rights, how
much more so when it comes to the right to bodily integrity?
6.
The responsibility argument sets a standard of strict liability that
imposes extreme burdens on the woman to avoid the punishment of
forced gestation. Effectively, her only options are complete
abstinence during her fertile years, having a hysterectomy, or having
a bilateral oophorectomy. All of
these options have severe consequences for a woman's total
well-being. There is no other case where we would impose
extraordinary burdens on someone to avoid strict liability.
7.
The responsibility argument does not address cases where the man
sabotaged the birth control.9
Though having sex in these conditions cannot be considered voluntary
(indeed, in some places sabotaging birth control legally constitutes sexual assault),
logically the responsibility argument will not excuse the woman.
True, her consent was conditioned upon properly using birth control,
but even using birth control does not reduce the risk of pregnancy to
zero. Since she would have still voluntarily taken the risk, she must
still accept the responsibility and can still be required to gestate.
8.
Even a rape victim may not be able to evade the strict liability
standard demanded by the responsibility argument. One could avoid
being raped by building an impregnable fortress and remaining inside
of it. By failing to do so, she assumes the risk of rape and, by the
terms of the responsibility argument, is therefore liable for the
results. Given that we live in a
rape culture where the woman is often, if not usually, blamed for the
rape as it is, this argument isn't as absurd as it might appear at
first glance.10
9.
The responsibility argument is not applied evenly. The same argument
would justify forced donations of blood, tissue, and organs when
someone caused the need. Yet anti-abortion advocates deny this implication.
10.
Anti-abortion advocates also try to say the responsibility argument
isn't about punishing women for having sex.
As it is, prohibiting abortion deprives pregnant women of their right
to life, liberty, and security of person; their right to be free from
slavery; their right to be recognized as a person before the law;
their right to equal protection under the law; their right to be free
from torture; their right to bodily integrity; and their right to
decide when and if to have children, all without due process of law.
The responsibility argument goes further than a blanket prohibition
of abortion though, precisely by claiming that this wholesale
deprivation of rights is justified because the woman had sex. The
responsibility argument turns sex into an act of negligence, if not a
crime.
11.
If abortion is prohibited on the basis of the responsibility
argument, it is inevitable that someone will die as a result of an
unwanted pregnancy. This means she will have been sentenced to the
death penalty for having sex. Even assuming the responsibility
argument can be sustained, we should rightly ask if the punishment
fits the crime. Death for having sex is completely incommensurate.
The
responsibility argument creates a prima
facie
case that the woman who engages in voluntary sex forfeits her bodily
autonomy by giving the prenate a claim to her body. This case does
not hold up under scrutiny. Though her participation in sex is
voluntary, it does not necessarily mean her choice was free. Even
granting that her choice was free, her responsibility for her
pregnancy is in itself questionable. The responsibility argument sets
up a standard that imposes excessive burdens on a woman trying to
avoid punishment. Advocates of the responsibility argument are not
consistent in applying the principle. Finally, even if it is granted
that the woman is responsible for her pregnancy, the punishment is
wholly disproportionate to the act she committed.
Edit: Changed the link to Thomson's "A Defense of Abortion" after one of the comments made me realize the html version here contained an error. The pdf version now linked also retains Thomson's footnotes, also omitted in the html version.
1I
wish to make it clear that I am discussing abortion as a political
issue, rather than a strictly moral one. My moral stance on
abortion, while still comparatively permissive, is more restrictive
than my political stance.
2Later
recognized in the case of McFall v. Shimp.
3Some
proponents will prefer to say that the right has actually been
waived rather than forfeited. Holly M. Smith decisively refuted that
notion in her paper “Intercourse and Moral Responsibility for the Fetus.”
4Most
people using the responsibility argument also exclude cases that
pose serious threats to the life and/or health of the mother.
Technically speaking, the life/health exception belongs to a
different category than the rape exception and is beyond the scope
of the responsibility argument.
5Other
cases may be exempt given the responsibility argument. For example,
a woman who engages in intercourse without the knowledge that sex
causes pregnancy would likely be exempt. It
is not my object to tease out all the possible exemptions. If my
counter-arguments are successful, then exceptions to the
responsibility argument becomes a moot issue.
6A
convicted criminal, for example, forfeits certain rights, including
freedom of movement, an aspect of bodily autonomy.
7I
realize that saying a person can be obligated to have sex will put
me on thin ice in some circles. While I am prepared to argue that in
some
circumstances, a person can be objectively obligated to have sex, I
need not have recourse to such an argument here. It is enough for
the purpose of this argument that the woman feel
some obligation to have sex, whether or not that feeling is based on
an objective duty.
8Or
not, when considering artificial insemination or in vitro
fertilization.
9Indeed,
in my experience, abortion opponents avoid the topic of reproductive coercion
in general. The exception is when the man attempts to force the
woman to have an abortion, which they use as a reason to prohibit
abortion.
10And
let's not forget Todd Akin's comments about “legitimate rape”
in this context.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)